In this post, I will discuss the first of two assumptions Augustine brought to his theological method. That assumption is the strong, or absolute omnipotence of God. All Christians believe God has all power. Not all Christians agree that he exercises that power in the same way. One of the things that makes this explanation tricky is that a lot of theo-philosophical water has gone under the bridge (e.g. nominalism and voluntarism) between Augustine's time and ours. It is difficult to use terminology to explain Augustine's position that has not been colored by movements since his time.
Perhaps here it would be best to distinguish what is meant by a strong view of divine omnipotence. The Christian faith has always asserted the omnipotence of God. Omnipotence has minimally been understood as God possessing all power, at least potentially. In simple terms, it means that God can do anything he wants that does not violate his character. Augustine certainly believed this and more. He elevated the omnipotence of God almost to the point of excluding humanity as agents who could make legitimate free choices. The key word in this sentence is "almost," because Augustine refined his ideas over a lifetime of writing. As well-known Augustine scholar Gerald Bonner summarizes Augustine's theological pilgrimage from freedom to grace, he writes that by the time Augustine penned Confessions (before 400), he "had come to accept the absolute primacy of divine grace in motivating all our thoughts and intentions, as well as providing the power to act." Bonner summarizes the point well:
It is easy to find quotations in his [Augustine's] writings which declare both God's omnipotence and human freedom of choice. In the end, however, for Augustine divine omnipotence triumphed, and he declared in 427: "In the solution of this question I indeed labored in defense of the free choice of the human will, but the grace of God conquered, and I was finally able to understand, with full clarity, the meaning of the Apostle: 'For who singles thee out? Or what hast thou that thou hast not received? But if thou hast received it, why dost thou boast as if thou hadst not received it?'" (1 Cor 4:7)
Thus Augustine settled on a strong view of omnipotence that human actions are from God as well. Much more could be gleaned from Augustine's writings which would show similar trains of thought, but what has been said so far may suffice. Commenting on his strong view of omnipotence, Ogliari writes, "The co-operation between God's intervention and the human being's desire, will and action, kept in theological balance during the first centuries, was undone in favor of a notion of God's infinite and absolute omnipotence; an omnipotence whose primacy and freedom of intervention could not be questioned or jeopardized by mankind's use of free will, whatever its potential." For Augustine, to be God means to be omnipotent in the strongest sense. And therefore here is the departure from the tradition he received. No Christian before him held to such a view of divine omnipotence. There was always room for true created freedom to operate. Before Augustine, divine sovereignty and human freedom existed together, even if the line between them was fuzzy. Augustine so emphasized divine sovereignty that human freedom became either radically minimized or extinguished altogether.
Why does Augustine settle on such a strong view of omnipotence? For Augustine, the created order is beautiful. The presence of evil in God's good world was both a philosophical and theological problem for the bishop of Hippo. Possibly the most vexing question in Augustine's mind was "Why evil?" As Lee writes, "Augustine is faced with the challenge of explaining the total goodness of the universe despite the presence of evil in it." Augustine believed he had come to a solution to this challenge by stating that the world remains beautiful and in order as long as sin is punished and the sinner is placed where he cannot disrupt the cosmic order. God therefore must be omnipotent in the strongest possible sense to be able to preserve the cosmic beauty of his creation by punishing sin. The power of God must be unlimited so that he can always preserve the beautiful order of his creation.
What then is the problem with Augustine's line of thinking? The problem lies in that he fails to balance divine omnipotence with genuine human freedom, especially in the very possible result that humans may choose to oppose God. Augustine writes, "But, however strong the wills either of angels or of men, whether good or evil, whether they will what God willeth or will something else, the will of the Omnipotent is always undefeated." Of course determinism follows immediately from that famous quote. Everything that occurs is ultimately the will of God, because it cannot be otherwise .The problem is not that Augustine was in blatant error; he had his truth out of balance, which allowed some of his students over the next 1500 years to become more out of balance.
When Augustine was a Manichean auditor, he grew dissatisfied with the lack of omnipotence in the Manichean principle of the good. John Rist writes, "Augustine not only wanted to follow the Christian (and Platonist) view that God is good, but the Christian view that he is all-powerful. He wanted to argue, in fact, that everything bad is either caused by a soul other than God, and is permitted by God for his 'good' reasons, or is inflicted by God for reasons of justice." He continues, "As we shall see, Augustine's continuing fear of God's 'weakness' is part of the explanation of his harsher attitude to the providential governance of the world." A weak God could not ensure the human soul's eternal pleasure in salvation, so he had to be strong—strong to the point of ordering everything to be just so.
Such a strong view of omnipotence causes immediate problems for the God described in Scripture. Throughout his career, Augustine juxtaposed the mercy of God in salvation with the justice of God in condemning sinners. Rist writes,
Augustine sees no difficulty about predicating all the traditional moral virtues such as justice, as well as the specially Jewish and Christian moral virtue of mercy, of this omnipotent God. Yet it is precisely his insistence that God is both omnipotent and just and merciful which causes him great difficulties in formulating an intelligible and convincing account of God as savior and redeemer of all mankind.
As Ogliari writes, "In the eyes of the bishop of Hippo, justice and mercy are two divine attributes of equal standing which manifest, respectively, God's 'due' condemnation of sin and God's 'undue' bestowal of grace." It is precisely on this point that Augustine's critics charged him with a latent Manichaeism, since in Augustine the justice and mercy of God could never be reconciled in the salvation of sinners.
There were two pivotal events in Augustine's life in the years before his monumental shift of his views of nature and grace. He had debates with two prominent North African Manichees—Faustus and Fortunatus. His debate with Fortunatus was especially important. Although Augustine claims he won the debate, a close study of his actions may prove otherwise. According to Jason Beduhn, Augustine began to shift his thinking toward Fortunatus' position immediately after his debate with him, claiming that Augustine adopted Fortunatus' grace-driven interpretation of Romans 9 as his own. He writes, "The system of intertextual exegesis of Paul that Augustine adopts is heavily influenced by Fortunatus. Augustine resists complete capitulation to Fortunatus' reasoning for some time. But by the end of the decade [the 390s], he has swung over entirely to Fortunatus' reading of Romans 7, and proceeds to go even further, past the Manichaean view of the embattled will, into a radical determinism." Augustine's cardinal assumption that the human soul is thoroughly evil forced him into a Manichaean reading of Paul in order to defend his position. (This point to be addressed more thoroughly in the next post)
Lee makes a powerful case that Augustine borrows conceptually from Manichaeism in formulating his views on nature and grace. More specifically, he argues that Augustine utilized the Manichaean concept of "good" for his own view of the "beautiful." In Lee's words, the "beautiful is "understood as that which engenders tranquil pleasure. To achieve tranquility through contemplation of the Supreme Good was the goal he set in his earliest writing, De pulchro et apto. This perspective continued to be at work in his insistence that God, as the Supreme Good, is the guarantor of the soul's tranquil enjoyment." He notes that the two main Manichaean influences in Augustine's thinking which contributed to his views on predestination are the hiddenness of God's grace and the inevitability of personal evil. Not to be overshadowed by Manichaeism, Neo-Platonism was a source of his assumptions as well. Reinhold Seeburg notes that the two key ideas Augustine borrowed from Neo-Platonism were "voluntarism (God is Will; man is will; love is blessedness) and Neo-Platonic intellectualism (the contemplation of the intelligible world is blessedness)." While Augustine's defenders will state he arrived at his position via Scripture, I think it will become clearer that he arrived philosophically first then read Scripture to fit his already-formulated ideas.
In the next post, Augustine's assumption of infralapsarian anthropology will be explored in detail. I welcome any comments and thanks for reading. I also want to apologize for the more academic nature of this post. I could not think of a good way to make it less academic and still make the point. Sorry for that. I'll try to do better in subsequent posts.
Dr. Gifford is Head of Department of General Studies and professor of theology and church history at New Life Theological Seminary, Charlotte, NC
Below are links to the entire series by Dr. Gifford:
- Coming Series on Saint Augustine and Southern Baptists by Dr. James D. Gifford Jr
- Augustine and Southern Baptists: an Introduction
- Augustine and Southern Baptists: Augustine and Divine Omnipotence
- Augustine and Southern Baptists: Augustine and Human Nature: Part 3A; Part 3B
- Augustine and Southern Baptists: The Upshot of Augustine's Assumptions: Divine Determinism
- Augustine and Southern Baptists: Augustine's Exegetical and Hermeneutical Method
- Augustine and Southern Baptists: Augustine's Critics and Legacy
Jim
This is outstanding even if "technical" in some ways. Albeit risking oversimplification, please offer us a "one-liner" in grasping both notions of nominalism and voluntarism.
Posted by: peter lumpkins | 2013.01.12 at 09:45 AM
All
I apologize for some formatting issues on the post. I'll fit it asap.
Posted by: peter | 2013.01.12 at 09:51 AM
Hi Peter,
This will be an oversimplification, of course, but...
Voluntarism is the belief that God is essentially will. It became popular in the 14th century with John Duns Scotus, though it was around long before him.
Nominalism is harder to put a finger on. It is a metaphysical approach that denies the reality of universals (abstract ideas that have their own independent existence apart from being instantiated in something). It became popular with William of Ockham and is the fountain from which both the modern ideal and the Protestant Reformers (esp. Luther and Zwingli) drank deeply.
Hope that helps a little.
Jim G.
Posted by: Jim G. | 2013.01.12 at 11:41 AM
Peter,
I'd like to add a few lines about nominalism. Platonic realism posits the objective existence of universals. This was found by realistic theologians to fit well with the already existent ideas of Biblical realism (the substantial, immaterial union of the race in Adam, first taught by Tertullian). In theological anthropology, the concept of the universal found its expression in the idea of an objective, immaterial, substantial union of the race in Adam, such that the race is propagated in its entire nature (both spiritual and physical). Nominalism denied that universals exist, and therefore concluded that there is no such thing as a racial union (or a union of any species), except for the union perceived by the observing mind. In other words, the mind observes that similarities exist between members of a species, and creates a mental category called species. This was the explicit denial that any real union of species exists. It was only the realists that held that specific union (or, union of species) was real, and hence they are called realists. To the nominalists the specific union was a union in name only (or, nominal), and hence they are called nominalists. While the realists located the union of man with Adam as within Adam himself (natural/Augustinian headship), the nominalists located that union within the mind of God (which eventually became federal/covenant headship).
The Protestant Reformers inconsistently held to both, being very much nominalists in general, but kept a realistic mode of thinking when it came to original sin. Adam's sin was imputed to us because it was our sin. As nominalism's influence grew, realism was discarded, and it was then taught that Adam's sin was ours merely because it was imputed. This brings up the second characteristic of nominalism: justice swallowed up in sovereignty. In this, the Calvinists from Turettin's day onward have a great difference between them and Augustine.
Jim, your article here is very interesting and brings up some questions that I'm sure you'll address in the coming installments, such as how Augustine's view did not allow justice and mercy to be reconciled in the salvation of sinners, so I'll wait.
Posted by: Ken Hamrick | 2013.01.12 at 01:14 PM
Thanks Ken. Good summary of nominalism. In my understanding of Augustine, the elect receive mercy while the non-elect sinners receive justice. I think he split apart these divine attributes more than Scripture does.
On a complete other note, I had a close relative back in W Va die and I need to go away for the funeral. I'll be out of pocket starting likely Monday until Wednesday or Thursday. If I can, I'll send Peter part 3 and maybe he can post it. I will likely not be able to interact until I return later in the week.
Jim G.
Posted by: Jim G. | 2013.01.12 at 06:23 PM
I'm sorry to hear that, Jim. Our prayers are with you and your family.
Posted by: Ken Hamrick | 2013.01.12 at 08:12 PM
Jim,
Amen to Ken's note. We wish you and your family the Lord's grace and much needed healing power at this difficult time while we look forward to your return. Do not feel pressured, however, that we meet a specific timeline. Our interest in this topic precludes walking away from such a timely theme.
Grace, brother...
Posted by: peter lumpkins | 2013.01.13 at 07:31 AM
Jim, Very sorry to hear the sad news. God Bless you and your family.
"To achieve tranquility through contemplation of the Supreme Good was the goal he set in his earliest writing, De pulchro et apto. This perspective continued to be at work in his insistence that God, as the Supreme Good, is the guarantor of the soul's tranquil enjoyment."
This concept sounds familiar:
"God is most glorified in us when we are most satisfied in him" John Piper, Christian Hedonism
Posted by: lydia | 2013.01.13 at 12:03 PM
Jim,
I appreciate the historical work you've done here and enjoyed reading it.
If you don't mind, I'd like to push you further with some of your assertions.
1. It's certainly no small thing to charge a hero of the faith with eisegesis in saying, "While Augustine's defenders will state he arrived at his position via Scripture, I think it will become clearer that he arrived philosophically first then read Scripture to fit his already-formulated ideas." Please help us see how Augustine's doctrine of God's omnipotence is not substantiated by Scripture.
2. As you well know, even a blind hog finds an acorn every now and then. What if Fortunatus and the Manichees were on to something in their grace-driven understanding of Romans 9? What exactly is this grace-driven Manichaean understanding of Romans 9 that apparently won Augustine? How did they misunderstand the text?
3. You quoted Augustine, "The will of the Omnipotent is always undefeated," and then postulated that this is problematic. Shouldn't libertarians agree with Augustine's statement also? Even from a libertarian viewpoint, God's will is not defeated because He wills that humans have the ability to choose otherwise. Isn't this the classic libertarian explanation that God is still sovereign even though He limits His sovereignty to allow libertarian freedom? Surely, you wouldn't say that the will of the Omnipotent is defeated, would you?
4. At this point, it seems to me that you are unintentionally poisoning the well concerning Augustine. You simply assert that Augustine borrowed conceptually from Manichaeism and Neo-Platonism, which pushes us to conclude that whatever Augustine believed, it must be wrong since the Manichees and Neo-Platonists were generally wrong. What exactly did he borrow? How is this not supported by Scripture?
5. It's certainly clear that you disagree with Augustine's formulation of the interaction between God's will and the human will. Would you define your understanding of God's omnipotence? Would you define your understanding of man's freedom? How do understand these two to interact?
Sorry, your article raised a lot of questions in my mind. Thanks!
Posted by: JBenSimpson | 2013.01.14 at 08:24 AM
Hi Ben,
I fear my replies will be too short to do your questions justice. As I stated in the thread above, my time is limited this week due to family circumstances, but here goes:
1. I'll make a separate post on Augustine's hermeneutical practice. I'll try to answer some of your objections there, but my circumstances may dictate the answer will be a couple weeks in coming. I hope that will be okay with you. Just know that if Augustine is correct in his hermeneutical method, it means that all who came before him were either ignorant or incorrect -- he deviated from the tradition that severely. I would certainly not be the first critic of his way of reading Scripture, from his lifetime until now.
2. This question requires a long answer I do not have the time to give today. The main track for an answer here is that the Manichees' teachings arose a couple of hundred years after the establishment of the church. They went against the received tradition on grace and taught something that no one had taught before them. The existing church rejected their interpretation. They also held personal evil as inevitable, which Augustine utilized in his the formation of his doctrine of grace. Again, he is deviating from the received tradition here. For us, that does not seem like such a big deal. But in the 4th-5th century (given apostolic succession), deviation is a really big no-no. More on this in my next post.
3. Of course you do realize the devil in is the details in this discussion. It is all in how the aspects (as we think we understand them) of God's will is divided. Although I have not run across a deep discussion of aspects of divine will in Augustine, I would think based on what I have read of him that he did not hold to a multi-valent division of aspects that libertarians do. Risking oversimplification, I read Augustine to say that the will of God is such that his omnipotence would guarantee that all that occurred would be his will, even if we cannot see how it all works out.
4. More will become clear in the next post on how he borrowed a couple of key ideas. I am not employing, as you fear, guilt by association. The areas where Augustine borrowed are the key areas where Christians (of all stripes) ought to disagree with Manichees and Neo-platonists.
5. To put it simply, I take the weaker view of omnipotence, that is, that God can do all things that do not contradict his own nature and integrity. I believe that God created this world in such a way that there are real contingencies in it, and room for real created freedom in both humans and angels. Where the exact line is drawn between God's power and human freedom remains a mystery to me. I will confess I do not know. I just know where it cannot be. It cannot be drawn so that neither God's power nor true created freedom are fully compromised. The world in which we live contains both the sovereignty of God and true created freedom. I believe the position at which Augustine settled compromised true created human freedom and thus departed from the received tradition.
Please give me until the end of the week to respond to any clarifications. I have 300+ miles to drive tonight and funeral and family tomorrow and Wednesday.
Jim G.
Posted by: Jim G. | 2013.01.14 at 12:40 PM
Hi Lydia,
Such is the sheer brilliance of Augustine. Love him or not, he anticipated so much that came after him. We all live in his shadow, one way or the other.
Jim G.
Posted by: Jim G. | 2013.01.14 at 12:42 PM
Jim,
Thanks for taking the time to reply. I know my questions required long answers, but I appreciate what you've replied thus far. I suppose I'll get more answers as well travel along this series. Just know that I'll do my best to point us back to Scripture as our ultimate judge and not the tradition of the church fathers pre-Augustine.
I pray mercy over your trip! Blessings!
Posted by: JBenSimpson | 2013.01.14 at 02:45 PM
As will mine :0)
Thanks for the kind words.
Jim G.
Posted by: Jim G. | 2013.01.14 at 03:32 PM